Index
to 'Across the Scales of Time'
Imagine a school classroom at work. What’s happening?
What are the characteristic timescales of the processes and events that make it
‘a classroom’ for us? Almost certainly people are talking, and their
actions, whether producing an utterance or writing at the chalkboard or handing
someone a scissors, cannot be understood, either as a selection from the
available repertory of human actions or in terms of timing and sequence (what
next? what, when?), apart from the meanings being made in talk and other forms
of action (for detailed descriptions and analyses of the particular classroom
scenes I have in mind as I write, see Lemke 1995, 1996, in press; Kamen et al.
1997; Roth 1998).
What are the characteristic timescales of the actions,
processes, and events we observe? Our immediate human interactional timescale
ranges from the glance and the word, said or done in a second or less, to the
complex sentence spoken or heard, the complex action performed over a few tens
of seconds. Evolution has tuned us to this narrow range of timescales; our
survival has depended for hundreds of millennia on noticing brief events (a
glimpse of predator through the brush) and sustaining short-term cooperative
action. But in the classroom, if we watch and listen long enough, we begin to
find repeating patterns (e.g. Mehan 1979, Lemke 1990): individual utterances of
certain semantic types (questions, answers, evaluations of answers) predictably
follow one another to constitute an exchange. There are identifiable types of
exchanges. These recur, recognizably for us and for the participants, not just
for a while, or among the same participants, but on different days, in different
situations, and even in different classrooms in different schools. They
constitute a cultural pattern or social semiotic formation (cf. Lemke
1995). Exchanges also enter into patterns on a still longer timescale; the ebb
and flow of talk, the shifts of topic and activity, divide the lesson into
episodes. Some types of episodes also recur. Episodes get integrated somehow
into lessons, and there are also lesson types, and even sequences of lesson
types (cf. Christie 19.. on ‘curriculum genres’) that recur across wide
geographical areas and which may
take days or weeks to complete. At these longer timescales there are curriculum
units and months- to years-long integrated curricula.
What about shorter timescales? Even an utterance of a
single word consists of recognizable and repeated sound patterns, the
articulation of the distinctive phonemes of a language, recognizable and
repeatable, though perhaps at the edge of our normal awareness. A typical
English vowel or short syllable takes about one-tenth of a second to articulate.
These articulations represent coordinations of fine muscle control by neuron
impulses acting at the few to tens of milliseconds scale, and they in turn sum
over neuron membrane depolarizations and ion and neurotransmitter flows that
occur on the millisecond timescale. Below that are still faster biochemical
reactions, but the scale of the fastest human actions is basically set by the
millisecond scale of neuron processes. No coordinated human action, not even
autonomic reflexes, can happen faster.
Table 1 shows the approximate timescales for each order of
magnitude above and below the 1 second focal scale of human action. At each
timescale we can recognize characteristic processes and social practices. For
adjacent timescales it is also quite clear that the processes at the next lower
timescale make possible the repeatable patternings of the next longer scale, in
accord with the reductionist model of systems hierarchies. What is equally
important, however, is that there is always also a higher level process already
in place, already running on its own longer timescale, and this sets the context
which constrains what is likely and what is socially appropriate at the next
scale below. A student’s answer to a teacher’s question is also meaningful
for the participants as part of an exchange, not just as an utterance in its own
right, and is judged as appropriate or not to the on-going exchange, and to the
episode, the lesson, the unit, the curriculum … and many higher-level
contexts. These contexts however are not static, they are themselves processes
unfolding in time. Very slow processes function like constant, static
backgrounds on the timescale of much faster processes.
Chemical synthesis
|
10-5 |
|
Neurotransmitter synthesis
|
Membrane process
|
10-4 |
|
Ligand
binding |
Neural firings
|
10-3 |
|
Neuron
process |
Neuronal patterns
|
10-2 |
|
Multi-neuron
process |
Vocal articulation |
10-1 |
|
Edge of awareness |
Utterance |
1-10 seconds |
|
Word, holophrase, short monologue; in context |
Exchange |
2- 102 |
Seconds to minutes |
Dialogue;
interpersonal relations ; developing situation |
Episode |
103 |
o(15 minutes) |
Thematic, functional unit; speech genre, educative |
Lesson |
103
– 104 |
Hour |
Curriculum
genre |
Lesson
sequence |
104 |
o(2.75
hours) |
Macro
curriculum genre |
School day |
105 |
Day |
[“seamless day”] |
Unit |
106 |
11.5 days |
Thematic, functional unit |
Unit sequence |
|
|
[rare] |
Semester/ Yr Curriculum |
107 |
4 Months |
Organizational level; unit in next scale |
Multi-year Curriculum |
108 |
o(3.2 years) |
Organizational level; limit of institutional planning |
Lifespan Educational Development |
109 |
o(32 years) |
Biographical timescale; Identity change |
Educational system change |
1010 |
o(320 years) |
Historical timescale; New institutions |
Note: o(time) means times on the order of
magnitude of ...
Worldsystem change |
1011 |
3200 years |
New cultures, languages; limit of historical
records |
Ecosystem, climate change |
1012 |
32,000 years |
|
|
1013 |
320,000 years |
Last ice age |
Evolutionary change |
1014 |
3.2 million years |
Scale of human evolution |
|
1015 |
32 million years |
Dinosaurs |
|
1016 |
317 million years |
Pangaea |
Planetary change |
1017 |
3.2 billion years |
Origin of life, of planet |
Universal change |
1018 |
32 billion years |
Cosmological processes |
It is useful to analyze scale hierarchies in groups of
three levels at once (cf. Salthe 1985, 1993; Lemke 1995, in press-b). Call the
middle level of any such group the focal level, or level N, the focus of
our interest for now. Dynamical systems theory basically says that processes
(and participants in those processes) can only interact directly and exchange
significant amounts of energy or information if they are on
the same scale. Technically this is only exactly true if we mean on the
same time scale (see discussion of the adiabatic principle below). What
is possible on the focal scale, the kinds of interactions that can
happen, depends on the kinds of processes and participants at the level
immediately below, level N-1. Processes at level N-1 are constitutive of
processes at level N; they provide the affordances for activity at level
N. But level N is never the top level (certainly for human social
processes); interactions on the focal level are not free to range over all the
possibilities afforded them: they are also constrained by being
themselves part of longer timescale processes at level N+1. The longer-scale
processes determine what is probable at the focal level. There are always
many ways in which the interactions at level N can satisfy the constraints of
level N+1, but the probability of each path depends in part on whether it is
consistent with the emerging patterns at level N+1.
It helps in understanding these inter-level relationships
to think of their history and origin. As interactions at some timescale become
linked, or coupled, and thus more interdependent, as they do in complex systems
of the kind we are interested in here, there are fewer and fewer possible
self-consistent patterns (cf. Kaufman 1993). In the origin of life, for example,
there were originally a lot of protein or RNA-like molecules mutually catalyzing
one another’s synthesis. As more new molecules were produced that could
function as potential catalysts for still more chemical reactions, eventually a
condition was reached where a few sequences of reactions formed a
self-sustaining cycle that then rapidly outpaced other reactions and entrained
most of the available nutrients into its own on-going patterns. The new patterns
were emergent, essentially allowed by the previous chemistry but not
required by it, and so unpredictable. The new cycles take more time, complete on
a longer timescale than the individual constituent reactions. They form a new
level of organization. From now on, any fluctuations in the concentrations of
chemicals in the pool are buffered by the existence of the new cycles, and
information which takes this form only reaches some still longer-scale (N+1)
process after being filtered or buffered by the new cycles. Once in place the
new cycles also alter the probability of reactions occurring on the level below
them, providing downwards constraints. And of course the new level now becomes
itself a potential unit of organization for something (like us) at a still
higher level to be built out of.
All new levels of organization emerge as intermediates
between pre-existing levels, and profoundly change the relations among the
formerly adjacent levels as well as making possible still newer emergent forms
(see discussion in Lemke, in press).
Are there emergent processes and patterns in classrooms? I
think every teacher and student knows that there are. There are new routines
that emerge, new social groupings and the typical interactions that sustain
them, class in-jokes, informal rituals, typical sayings and phrasings, favorite
word usages with special meanings, etc. These in turn can become the raw
material for more complex new patterns unique to the classroom, and they
certainly constrain the probabilities of actions and utterances which would
invoke these special meanings or contribute positively or negatively to social
relationships. A classroom, and indeed every human community, is an
individual at its own scale of organization. It has a unique historical
trajectory, a unique development through time. But like every such individual on
every scale, it is also in some respects typical of its kind. That
typicality reflects its participation in still larger-scale, longer term, more
slowly changing processes, which shape not only its development but also that of
others of its type.
A classroom community can be taken as a whole on its longest timescale of activity, typically a few months to a year. We can ask how it develops, as an individual and as a typical instance of its kind. Subject to what constraints from which still larger-scale processes? Made possible by which characteristics of which shorter timescale processes? We can look at its component processes and constitutive units as well, each on their own timescales. And here things begin to get rather complex, because we can easily see that, for example, a social grouping may form that lasts longer than the classroom community. Is it a unit within the classroom community, or a unit at a higher scale? What about a textbook? It is surely the product of a larger-scale, longer-term process (of writing, editing, publishing, etc.), and so a participant in processes on those scales, but it also seems to be a small-scale participant in short-term events within the classroom (e.g. reading aloud a homework problem at the end of a chapter). To understand such phenomena we need to understand the two different principles that seem to govern relationships across scales: the adiabatic principle, and the principle of semiotically mediated heterochrony.